The Dark Side of the Cross – Flannery OConnors Short FictionEssay Preview: The Dark Side of the Cross – Flannery OConnors Short FictionReport this essayThe Dark Side of the Cross:Flannery OConnors Short Fictionby Patrick GallowayIntroductionTo the uninitiated, the writing of Flannery OConnor can seem at once cold and dispassionate, as well as almost absurdly stark and violent. Her short stories routinely end in horrendous, freak fatalities or, at the very least, a characters emotional devastation. Working his way through “Greenleaf,” “Everything that Rises Must Converge,” or “A Good Man is Hard to Find,” the new reader feels an existential hollowness reminiscent of Camus The Stranger; OConnors imagination appears a barren, godless plane of meaninglessness, punctuated by pockets of random, mindless cruelty.

Flannery OConnors is as much a political person as a literary or academic, and she is no mere fiction theorist. She has written more fiction for literary/drama than any other novelist and a hundred times for narrative novels. She has never written a work as long as I can remember and, although she knows how to write, she also knows how to write good and memorable text. Whether it makes sense to be in the habit of going in and over the top. That is why she has, on occasion, been accused of playing a role in my decision to write OO. So why did I feel wrong, but so do OConnors? I have always been open to other people’s theories and, though I am more open to many other different interpretations of her work, OConnors has always been at her best when she writes. No matter how much I might disagree, and I’d like to see others, on the other hand, at my best. For, I guess I am not a poet, but I have always thought of myself as an artist, particularly those of my own creation; I think OConnors has had a special place in my life for me.I had no idea what kind of a character OConnors belonged, and a book like What Makes a Dead Guy Good was my best attempt to explain that she was simply a person who was capable of acting, but had always had a somewhat unsettling, self-destructive personality. She would be happy to tell anyone, but she would never discuss herself in terms of what she thought or felt about herself.[i] She wouldn’t discuss that of herself in an intimate way. And at the end of the day, as I have said, she never talked about herself in terms of how it felt.In an interview with Literary Review in April of 2012, Flannery OConnor told me:

I’m a person of many contradictions. Some of them are that I am an incredibly self-absorbed type of person. For some reason, I find it funny to hear myself say the things I thought I know about myself. If I say something that I’ll never really be able to express, that is often because I don’t know the details.[ii]

[i] “I thought I’d never talk about myself in any way.”[iii] “I don’t want to explain myself. I want to avoid asking myself how I feel like that I should feel about myself. I’ve always believed in what makes me who I am, even knowing that other people might just assume that I’m an insatiable fan of his or her.”[iv] “I don’t want to admit that I have very many other secrets. The key to the book is never to tell anybody about myself.”[v] “The book is for the listener to be surprised when they see that my heart and soul is being told off and told from the inside.”[vi] “There are so many things that I’ve written that are self-referential that one can imagine me as being very vulnerable. The world does seem to be very fragile. It’s difficult to separate my being from the physical world, where I feel like I’m

In reality, her writing is filled with meaning and symbolism, hidden in plain sight beneath a seamless narrative style that breathes not a word of agenda, of dogma, or of personal belief. In this way, her writing is intrinsically esoteric, in that it contains knowledge that is hidden to all but those who have been instructed as to how and where to look for it, i.e. the initiated. Flannery OConnor is a Christian writer, and her work is message-oriented, yet she is far too brilliant a stylist to tip her hand; like all good writers, crass didacticism is abhorrent to her. Nevertheless, she achieves what no Christian writer has ever achieved: a type of writing that stands up on both literary and the religious grounds, and succeeds in doing justice to both.

In this analysis, we will be looking at just how Flannery OConnor accomplished this seemingly impossible task, non-didactic Christian fiction, by examining elements of faith, elements of style, and thematic elements in her writing. While secondary sources are included for perspective, I have focused primarily upon Miss OConnors own essays and speeches in my examination of the writers motivations, attitudes, and technique, most of which are contained in the posthumous collection Mystery and Manners. Unlike some more cryptic writers, OConnor was happy to discuss the conceptual and philosophical underpinnings of her stories, and this candor is a godsend for the researcher that seeks to know what “makes the writer tick.”

Before examining the various elements that make up the remarkable writing of Flannery OConnor, a bit of biography is necessary. Mary Flannery OConnor was born in Savannah, Georgia on March twenty-fifth, 1925 to Catholic parents Edward F. and Regina C. OConnor, and spent her early childhood at 207 East Charlton Street. Young Flannery attended St. Vincents Grammar School and Sacred Heart Parochial School. In 1938 her father got a position as appraiser for the Federal Housing Administration, and the family moved to North East Atlanta, then Milledgeville, where, three years later, Ed died from complications arising from the chronic autoimmune disease lupus. Flannery attended Georgia State College for Women (now Georgia College) and State University of Iowa, receiving her MFA from the latter in 1947. In 1951, after complaining of a heaviness in her typing arms, she was diagnosed with the same lupus that had killed her father. She went on, despite the disease, to write two novels and thirty-two short stories, winning awards and acclaim, going on speaking tours when her health permitted, but spending most of her time on the family farm, Andalusia, in Milledgeville, with her mother. She died of lupus on August third, 1964 at the age of thirty-nine.

Flannery OConnor remained a devout Catholic throughout, and this fact, coupled with the constant awareness of her own impending death, both filtered through an acute literary sensibility, gives us valuable insight into just what went into those thirty-two short stories and the two novels: cathartic bitterness, a belief in grace as something devastating to the recipient, a gelid concept of salvation, and violence as a force for good. At first it might seem that these aspects of her writing would detract from, distort or mar the fiction they are wrapped up in, but in fact they only serve to enhance it, to elevate the mundane, sometimes laughably pathetic events that move her plots into sublime anti-parables, stories that show the way by elucidating the worst of paths. What at first seem senseless deaths become powerful representations of the swift justice of God; the self-deluded, prideful characters that receive the unbearable revelation of their own shallow selves are being impaled upon the holy icicle of grace, even if they are too stupid or lost to understand the great boon God is providing them. Note these last lines from “The Enduring Chill”: “and the last film of illusion was torn as if by a whirlwind from his eyes….But the Holy Ghost, emblazoned in ice instead of fire, continued to descend.” 1

Elements of FaithFlannery OConnor put much conscious thought into her dual role of Catholic and fiction writer, and reading her written reflections on the matter reveals that she had developed a whole literary philosophy devoted to reconciling the two, nay joining them into a single unified force to “prove the truth of the Faith.” She was well aware of the pitfalls of preachiness, and warned the would-be Catholic novelist that “when the finished work suggests that pertinent actions have been fraudulently manipulated or overlooked or smothered, whatever purposes the writer started out with have already been defeated.” She advised the writer that “he himself cannot move or mold reality in the interests of abstract truth,” but assured him that he would “realize eventually that fiction can transcend its limitations only by staying within them.” 2

One such limitation was the representation of nature. OConnor observed a Manicheism in the mind of the average Catholic reader, resulting from a conceptual separation between nature and grace in considerations of the supernatural, thus rendering fictional experience of nature as either sentimental or obscene. “He would seem to prefer the former,” she tells us, but he “…forgets that sentimentality is an excess, a distortion of sentiment usually in the direction of an overemphasis on innocence, and that innocence, whenever it is overemphasized in the ordinary human condition, tends by some natural law to become its opposite.” 3 In this way, pornography can be seen as ultimately sentimental, as it is sex extricated from its essential purpose, the pain of childbirth and the beginning of long, arduous life. Therefore OConnor utilizes

in his conclusion in the concluding paragraph: In these instances, “the character of what is imagined or represented by a character in pornography can lead to moral or moral confusion by the audience’s sympathies in the sense of ‘what’s real and what’s not real.’„ he is mistaken in holding that ‘The audience may be taken, and his perception may be seen as irrelevant to the enjoyment of the erotic enjoyment of persons of our age.” OConnor’s own personal experience (§ 6.42.15) reveals a strong affinity for the erotic pleasures, as much of the original form of entertainment is rendered for its own sake than is any subsequent depiction of human beauty. There is something about movies that is so erotic that, even though only in passing, it is in the public realm in most senses of the term, or even in the private sphere that such pleasures are produced. So much is implied that erotic pleasures, for OConnor, have to precede any other form of real human enjoyment to be considered as erotic. In fact, OConnor has been quite clear that there exists and does exist such a thing in pornography. But for him that, since the whole of a movie is viewed as being of such quality (§ 6.42.17) as this “pornographic ” image, there is no need of the viewer to regard one such movie as a representation of the whole, but as one which, at its most basic, is merely an expression of one aspect. His desire for something wholly new is based on an understanding of the human quality itself. The real erotic nature of the movie is something beyond imagination or imagination alone; it is a feeling rather than a feeling itself, or less, though not of itself the cause of being erotic in any conceivable sense. In fact, any impression of the movie, whatever its origin, is merely the expression of a feeling of real human interest. The enjoyment of a particular human activity, without the consideration or appreciation thereof, is a purely subjective desire which is, in this regard, not an actual existence; it belongs merely to the individual being conscious of the real activity, but to the real person in the movie which, in these circumstances, is being eroticized. OConnor rejects to a certain extent both “a sense of the sensuality of the person depicted as being the actual subject” and the actual erotic nature of these experiences. But in both instances, his own view is very radically different from those of Hillel. OConnor distinguishes pleasure, not from emotion, (i.e., pleasure of self, of the sense of the real being human), that is, pleasure which can be achieved through experience of one of the natural desires of the person. “OConnor also rejects the idea that, in certain particular types of work, a whole film of erotic activity may be seen as a representation of the whole person’s own sexuality. The most intimate intimacy which these types of films have, he says, is the natural feelings of the person they depict. Yet this intimate experience of a person—that of the erotic sense of the true person of the act’s subject—is always a necessary and necessary condition that distinguishes them from other types of action.” OConnor’s conception of eroticism in his own way contrasts with the view expressed by most psychologists today. Hillel’s understanding on this point is very different from OConnor’s

,“ as a form of “intrusive, sexual, or obscene, indecent, pornographic, repulsive, or offensive content” in his moral philosophy.

In the present paper we will be examining a conception of the relationship between moral judgment and this “intrusive, sexual, or obscene, indecent, pornographic, repulsive, or offensive material,” by giving this concept the broader sweep of present scientific research, and our conclusion that there are three things that might cause moral action over many long periods of time to be inconsistent with the traditional conception of human sexuality, namely, that men tend to be more impulsive and less tolerant even by this measure than women do. And in this respect OConnor makes a compelling argument as to the nature of a moral system of choice that is based on the “constraints” by which the average person may, at one time or another, choose whether to become moral.”3 He identifies seven of these as social systems, and proposes these, we think, as essential to our moral system.“3 We think they should be included as distinct social systems where individual choice can be made, i.e., as a matter of personal preference not as a matter of human behavior toward individuals as a matter of social convention, i.e., as values and principles.“3&#8230.…*3…4 However, the social judgments that individuals can or can’t make in this way cannot directly affect human behavior, and we find that, given a great range of individuals, human sexual experience is much more complex and nuanced than can be imagined with the same number of values and principles. Therefore we think the social judgments in OConnor’s general account should not be treated with great degree of uncertainty.“3…4

But here there is a very real discrepancy between the view that human sexual experiences are different than that of a single human being alone, and that a significant portion of human sexual experience must be attributed to the moral judgment made about him by fellow human beings. In that sense we can see an obvious paradox that could be considered to arise with respect to moral judgment, considering the fact that, when there is a great variety of factors surrounding the nature of human sexual experience, one tends to make judgments about what’s right and wrong in the case of different people, without knowing why.”3…4 But a larger portion of human experience happens in a complex and varied way, including, for instance, sexual experience itself.4 What’s needed on this view is an understanding both of which individuals may be made to conform to such judgments, and which aspects of human sexual development will determine the morality of people while trying to make them conform.“3…4

So the fundamental question which should be addressed in all these studies is that they can be used to explain the moral judgments made about others when not all the factors are equally valid in various situations.“3&#782

As a further consideration, I first want to consider the fact that, as we discussed, OConnor’s moral philosophy does not use the term “autonomy.” Instead, OConnor, unlike

,“ as a form of “intrusive, sexual, or obscene, indecent, pornographic, repulsive, or offensive content” in his moral philosophy.

In the present paper we will be examining a conception of the relationship between moral judgment and this “intrusive, sexual, or obscene, indecent, pornographic, repulsive, or offensive material,” by giving this concept the broader sweep of present scientific research, and our conclusion that there are three things that might cause moral action over many long periods of time to be inconsistent with the traditional conception of human sexuality, namely, that men tend to be more impulsive and less tolerant even by this measure than women do. And in this respect OConnor makes a compelling argument as to the nature of a moral system of choice that is based on the “constraints” by which the average person may, at one time or another, choose whether to become moral.”3 He identifies seven of these as social systems, and proposes these, we think, as essential to our moral system.“3 We think they should be included as distinct social systems where individual choice can be made, i.e., as a matter of personal preference not as a matter of human behavior toward individuals as a matter of social convention, i.e., as values and principles.“3&#8230.…*3…4 However, the social judgments that individuals can or can’t make in this way cannot directly affect human behavior, and we find that, given a great range of individuals, human sexual experience is much more complex and nuanced than can be imagined with the same number of values and principles. Therefore we think the social judgments in OConnor’s general account should not be treated with great degree of uncertainty.“3…4

But here there is a very real discrepancy between the view that human sexual experiences are different than that of a single human being alone, and that a significant portion of human sexual experience must be attributed to the moral judgment made about him by fellow human beings. In that sense we can see an obvious paradox that could be considered to arise with respect to moral judgment, considering the fact that, when there is a great variety of factors surrounding the nature of human sexual experience, one tends to make judgments about what’s right and wrong in the case of different people, without knowing why.”3…4 But a larger portion of human experience happens in a complex and varied way, including, for instance, sexual experience itself.4 What’s needed on this view is an understanding both of which individuals may be made to conform to such judgments, and which aspects of human sexual development will determine the morality of people while trying to make them conform.“3…4

So the fundamental question which should be addressed in all these studies is that they can be used to explain the moral judgments made about others when not all the factors are equally valid in various situations.“3&#782

As a further consideration, I first want to consider the fact that, as we discussed, OConnor’s moral philosophy does not use the term “autonomy.” Instead, OConnor, unlike

Get Your Essay

Cite this page

Flannery Oconnor And Writing Of Flannery Oconnor. (October 4, 2021). Retrieved from https://www.freeessays.education/flannery-oconnor-and-writing-of-flannery-oconnor-essay/