On the Knowledge of Mind: Malebranche V. DescartesEssay Preview: On the Knowledge of Mind: Malebranche V. DescartesReport this essayHeavily inspired by Descartes, Malebranche examines the human mind in The Search After Truth. Both philosophers acknowledge that the existence of the mind is better known than that of the body; however, Malebranche claims that the body can ultimately be known better than the mind. This is in direct response to Descartes claim that the mind is better known than the body. After examining Descartes claims, we will then examine Malebranches counter-claims and analyze his strongest arguments against Descartes. Finally, possible responses by Descartes accompanied by an examination of the philosophical bases of both writers may help to show that Malebranche does not effectively serve to disprove Descartes claim.
For Descartes, certainty of knowledge can be obtained by first doubting everything that can be doubted and then assenting only to clear and distinct ideas. The subject of Descartes Second Meditation is the nature of the human mind and “that it is better known than the body.1” After withdrawing from his body, Descartes exists as a mere thinking thing- one who can doubt, understand, affirm, deny, will, refuse, imagine and sense (AT 7.28). The realization that he is thinking is sufficient for Descartes to prove his existence, at least as a thinking thing. Next, Descartes finds himself full of ideas, each with their own true nature; and subsequently, he finds it significant that all these things belong to him. Thus, through realization of his existence and that he contains ideas, Descartes has arrived at some knowledge of the mind.
In his Principles of Philosophy, Descartes elaborates on the definition of a substance. This definition helps explain arguments of how the body is better known than the mind.
Descartes, R. Meditations, Objections, and Replies. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing, 2006. All future references will refer to standard Adam and Tannery (AT) numbers.
Descartes believes a substance, or independently existing thing, is characterized by its principal attribute. These principal attributes seem to be equivalent to the essence of the substance. In addition to this principal attribute, substances may have also have modes. Relating this definition to our subject, Descartes believes that the essence or principal attribute of the mind is thought and that ideas are modes of mind.
Given that bodies can be perceived only by the intellect and not by the untrustworthy senses, the intellect must be the ultimate faculty. As the essence of mind is understanding, intellect, or thought, Descartes reasons that “nothing can be perceived more easily and more evidently than my own mind” (AT 7.34). The nature of the mind is so manifest to Descartes that he admits that anything learned from the consideration of bodies will also help to make the mind better known. The idea that knowledge of bodies leads to better knowledge of the mind is expanded in the Fifth Replies when Descartes claims a direct correspondence between these types of knowledge (AT 7.360). For every attribute known about bodies, we learn that the mind has the power to know these attributes. According to Descartes 11th Principle, he reasons that this relationship arises because the natural light shows us that the clearness of our knowledge is in direct proportion with the number of qualities we know about it. He repeats this idea in the Fifth Replies, arguing that given we understand a substance through its attributes, if we know more attributes then more complete is our understanding of its nature. Descartes concludes that it should be sufficient proof that our knowledge of existence and the essence of the mind leads to a clear idea of the mind. If, however, this is insufficient, then the number of attributes we know about the mind is yet more proof reflective of its distinct nature.
Recognizing bodies as “the most distinctly grasped of all” (AT 7.30), Descartes proceeds to examine a piece of wax. Removing everything not belonging to the wax, he was left with the essence of bodies: extension. After learning the essence of bodies, Descartes claims that his faculty of imagination provides clear and distinct images of bodies (AT 7.72). However, neither the senses nor the imagination but only pure intellection is sufficient proof for their existence. Descartes, as he does not attribute imagination to the essence of mind, believes the difference between imagination and pure intellection may lead to bodily intuitions of ideas that can then be understood by the mind or perceived by the senses. These ideas are “much more vivid and explicit and even, in their own way, more distinct than any of those that I deliberately and knowingly formed” (AT 7.75). Also, because “there is nothing that this nature [i.e. God himself or the ordered network of created things instituted by God] teaches me more explicitly than that I have a body” (AT 7.80), we should not doubt that there is some truth in this (ibid). If God is not a deceiver, the God-given inclinations to believe in corporeal things and the clear and distinct ideas arising from them serve to corroborate the existence of bodies. In the First Replies, Descartes goes as far as saying he can “completely understand what a body is when I think that it merely has extension and shape, is capable of moving; and so on” (AT 7.120).
Now we must examine Malebranche corresponding views on the knowledge of mind. Agreeing that evidence consists in clear and distinct perceptions, Malebranche believes that knowledge of body and knowledge of mind are achieved respectively through ideas and through consciousness or inner sensation. As we gain access to knowledge of the soul through consciousness, and not by its idea or through God, our knowledge of the soul is consequently imperfect, as it lacks clear and distinct evidence2. Though our idea of the soul may not be complete, Malebranche believes that we know enough to demonstrate the immortality, spirituality, freedom, and other attributes of the soul.
Malebranche is more precise in his explanation of how we know bodies. His argument is that “undoubtedly, we know bodies with their properties through ideas, because given that they are not intelligible by themselves, we can perceive them only in that being which contains them in an intelligible wayÐ.The knowledge we have of them is quite perfectЖi.e. our idea of extension suffices to inform us of all the properties of which extension is capable” (Search 3.2.7.3). In the Sixth Elucidation on the existence of bodies, Malebranche reasons that given we have an inclination to believe in bodies, there is more reason to believe in favor for their existence than against it. Also, because these natural judgments are in accordance with faith, we can form a judgment
† of bodies or people? And as a result, he makes it a question of what type of opinion we should adopt. The answer is that our mind consists of a series of facts, formed from the facts that we know—all that we know (in a natural way, in that order or the manner in which they are formed) that are known not only by reference to ourselves, but both of ourselves as well, by reference to things. In other words, he says: it would seem that, at least from the conception of body, we can determine which types of bodies to follow as persons in a natural way, by looking for these things, and in the various ways that they can be observed and observed! How we may answer this question is by means of the following points. First, the truth of the subject may be shown by experience, so that we may think and judge of the whole subject. Second, because the subject is of a different order from the body, the order must still be known, because the idea of a body by it will be given by the perception and a description of those bodies; as if we felt that the same body was in order, with it, a different body, so we may be sure that it was composed the same, or both order—and at least as far as we were able to tell about the existence of the subject, being of different order or order from the body. Furthermore, all bodies have properties or properties which can be distinguished with exact certainty, or which are certain from certainty. Such is the nature of things and things which differ from one another under one rule, and even under the influence of some other law. And, as it was from the same order and order that men were born, so it may be said, that the body is composed of three parts, or parts which are different, for so in some respects are different, and in others differ in degree, or in the order of their parts. As each of these parts is different in its relation to the other, there is something similar in the parts of men, as well as in all the parts of women, which are different, and which may, as it were, be thought to be the same persons. In other circumstances, the man is the cause of man’s existence by that very law of inheritance and necessity, but in that case he alone can be the cause; which means that he would have no claim to be like man, and as such would become a natural extension of the original body, without possessing the natural property which is characteristic of an artificial being, and which are made of the same properties, since this is the same for all things produced by natural law. Thus, if this be the case, then the body consists of certain characteristics, and is different from it, and therefore it is necessary for man to be created by the laws of nature, which are contrary to the natural laws. And it may also be said that any