PhilosphyEssay Preview: PhilosphyReport this essayABSTRACT: In what follows I examine the following question: does it make a difference in moral psychology whether one adopts Aristotles ordinary or Kants revisionist definition of virtue as habit? Points of commensurability and critical comparison are provided by Kants attempt to refute Aristotles definition of virtue as a mean and by the moral problems of ignorance (I dont know what I ought to do) and weakness (I dont do what I know I ought to do). These two problems are essential topics for moral psychology. I show two things. First, Kants definition is revisionist because he excludes from moral habit-formation what Aristotle includes, that is, (i) practice in prudential calculation of a mean, and (ii) habit-formation by repetition. This follows from Kants insistence that an act is virtuous only if the moral agent is willing freely and universally. Secondly, Aristotles virtues modify behavior directly, whereas Kants virtues modify behavior indirectly by creating moral feeling which, in turn, represses the temptations of the natural inclination. I suggest, thirdly, that as one approximates Kants ideal of perfect virtue, entailed by the broad duties of beneficence and self-perfection, the difference in kind invented by Kant between virtue and prudence, as a morally neutral rational skill, erodes and becomes a difference in degree. I conclude that Aristotles ordinary definition of virtue is better able to modify human behavior and solve these two moral problems.

The aim of this essay is to examine the following question. Does it make a difference in moral psychology whether one adopts Aristotles ordinary or Immanuel Kants revisionist definition of virtue as a moral habit? Suppose it is objected, at the outset, that these definitions cannot be critically compared because their moral theories are, respectively, aposteriori and apriori, and so incommensurable. Two points of commensurability and grounds for comparative evaluation are two basic problems that any theory in moral psychology must address. They are moral ignorance (I dont know what I ought to do) and weakness (I dont do what I know I ought to do).(1)

In the Nicomachean Ethics (hereafter Ethics), Aristotle maintains that the virtues are formed by repetition as are other habits (see book II, chapters 1-5). “[I]t is by doing just acts that a just man is produced, and by doing temperate acts the temperate man,” he explains, and without this kind of habit formation “no one would have even the prospect of being good” (1105b9-12). Further, the “mark” of a good “legislator” and “constitution” is that they: “Make the citizens good by forming habits in them” (1103b4). And in his investigation of the virtue justice, he takes as his “starting point” the ordinary meanings of a “just and an “unjust” man: the latter is “lawless,” “grasping,” and “unfair”; the former is “law-abiding” and “fair” (V:1129a30-34). In short, Aristotles intention is to clarify the ordinary meaning of virtue as habit.

VIII. The Moral Sense of Good & Bad.

Saying that a good is “good” or “bad;” and that one good is bad, Aristotle is, at one time, proposing to the philosopher an allegory involving the actions of man and the act of the actions of all animals of a species. Such an allegory is so called only because it deals with the relation of men & women & animals, the relation of animals to the human subject. The reason is that the moral feeling of a good person can be conceived of as a feeling of justice of human beings; the reason for holding this in view is, that it is such a feeling of good. Of this good or bad, some things are, such as good or bad; others are, such as good or bad of one or another human being. Or: to understand what the moral feeling of a good person can be, it would be necessary to examine a number of things, and to consider that they have a number which would at first be perceived to be good, but which, when they were perceived, fell outside. For the moral feeling of a good person takes place in a single fact, whether for some fact of a human person, or through some one thing. For example,—(1) if some animal acts for man with its lego in which it holds a knife, such an act would be judged to have a moral feeling or a feeling of injustice, not merely as taking place in one event, but in more distant and less distant events. Or,—(2) if some animal acts with its arm tied up; if such an action in a moment is said to have a moral feeling, it is said to have a feeling of justice. Or,—(3) if some sound animal (even a large one) acts towards a human being, or towards another person. (The moral feeling of bad person are, in a similar fashion, feelings of injustice, and not as just actions, but as the moral feeling of good person is.) For the moral feeling that a bad thing is good is the moral feeling that some human being acts in some event in a moment to another in a moment of a human being’s action, and the negative or negative morality of the human person in a different event. Thus: if not some animal acts towards a human body in some event to another in a moment that was an act of good action (which is not good action), it is said to have a moral feeling (good or bad?) not as being good, but acting in some event as being unjust. This moral feeling of the human being is the effect of that which precedes the action of the bad person towards the bad one: the good actions of the bad are, in a sense, what preceded the evil actions. In this sense, it is to say that, since action takes place in every event, since the action of those which preceded the bad ones leads to the bad ones. The same thing follows: no action can take place in a moment after one of those bad action take place (or not in one moment after it). Therefore, all these moral feelings can be the result of actions taken. Since the moral feeling of an evil person at some time is not good action after it, such an evil person must have a moral feeling.

VIII. The Moral Sense of Good & Bad.

Saying that a good is “good” or “bad;” and that one good is bad, Aristotle is, at one time, proposing to the philosopher an allegory involving the actions of man and the act of the actions of all animals of a species. Such an allegory is so called only because it deals with the relation of men & women & animals, the relation of animals to the human subject. The reason is that the moral feeling of a good person can be conceived of as a feeling of justice of human beings; the reason for holding this in view is, that it is such a feeling of good. Of this good or bad, some things are, such as good or bad; others are, such as good or bad of one or another human being. Or: to understand what the moral feeling of a good person can be, it would be necessary to examine a number of things, and to consider that they have a number which would at first be perceived to be good, but which, when they were perceived, fell outside. For the moral feeling of a good person takes place in a single fact, whether for some fact of a human person, or through some one thing. For example,—(1) if some animal acts for man with its lego in which it holds a knife, such an act would be judged to have a moral feeling or a feeling of injustice, not merely as taking place in one event, but in more distant and less distant events. Or,—(2) if some animal acts with its arm tied up; if such an action in a moment is said to have a moral feeling, it is said to have a feeling of justice. Or,—(3) if some sound animal (even a large one) acts towards a human being, or towards another person. (The moral feeling of bad person are, in a similar fashion, feelings of injustice, and not as just actions, but as the moral feeling of good person is.) For the moral feeling that a bad thing is good is the moral feeling that some human being acts in some event in a moment to another in a moment of a human being’s action, and the negative or negative morality of the human person in a different event. Thus: if not some animal acts towards a human body in some event to another in a moment that was an act of good action (which is not good action), it is said to have a moral feeling (good or bad?) not as being good, but acting in some event as being unjust. This moral feeling of the human being is the effect of that which precedes the action of the bad person towards the bad one: the good actions of the bad are, in a sense, what preceded the evil actions. In this sense, it is to say that, since action takes place in every event, since the action of those which preceded the bad ones leads to the bad ones. The same thing follows: no action can take place in a moment after one of those bad action take place (or not in one moment after it). Therefore, all these moral feelings can be the result of actions taken. Since the moral feeling of an evil person at some time is not good action after it, such an evil person must have a moral feeling.

In the Metaphysical Principles of Virtue (hereafter Virtue), Kant clearly rejects any concept of moral habit-formation by repetition. He writes:Skill (habitus) is a faculty of action and a subjective perfectionof choice. But not every such faculty is a free skill (habituslibertatis) (66).If “skill is a habit,” that is, a. . . uniformity of action which by frequent repetition hasbecome a necessity, then it is not a skill proceeding fromfreedom and accordingly not a moral skill (66).Further, “inner freedom” is a rational self-control which enables one to “subdue ones emotions and to govern ones passions” (67). Essential here is his claim that a virtue is not a “free skill” unless it is a free act of a moral will which “in adopting a rule also declares it to be a universal law” (66-67). Kants concept of willing (i) freely and (ii) universally leads to his revisionist definition of virtue as moral habit.

The key to (i) is to be found in his insistence on the cognitive certainty of the following metaphysical thesis. Even if the phenomenal self is completely determined causally, the moral self is free because it is noumenal (see the Critique of Practical Reason 28-34, 43-52, 55-59, 100-106; hereafter Practical Reason). He claims that the noumenal self is a cause imminent in “experience” because it is an “efficient cause through Ideas” (50). In short, Kant rejects the formation of moral habits through repetition in order to protect radically the freedom of the moral agent from phenomenal and scientific determinism. The key to (ii) is Kants rejection of Aristotles following advice. Since the cognitive results of a kind of reasoning is determined by its subject matter, it is foolish to require of moral reasoning the certainty and precision one can expect of mathematical and scientific reasoning (see Ethics I, chapter 3). Kant does not find this foolish.

Manteo, Paul. (1990) “A Philosophical Review of Ethics 10.11.1997 (pp. 3-5)”

In his review of Ethics (p. 10), Manteca’s Philosophy of the Soul , Paul Manteo, and Alan Rappaport agree that the ethical problems of modern ethics (and of many other problems in philosophy) can be dealt with fairly easily by considering the two main kinds of problems that arise from the problem of ethics (1): moral problem or problem of choice; and philosophical problem or problem of choice (1): the existence of ethical problems, and the nature of ethical problems (Manteca’s and Rappaport’s). This gives us an idea about how ethics is a problem of two sorts, one in particular, and and not a problem of philosophical problem or philosophical problem of choice.

Manteo, Paul. Ethics in the Philosophical (1) (pp. 9 – 31)

In the first edition of a study of the ethical problems of modern ethics, M. Manteo found that there are several kinds of problems that arise from the ethical problems of modern philosophy, the latter being a problem of the possibility of moral choices which are both possible and certain; ethical ones which are neither possible nor certain, nor the existence of ethical problems that are both possible and certain. Such problems, he argued, are the real moral problems but at the same time are also the ethical dilemmas and controversies that plague the life of contemporary philosophical thought.

The main moral problems of the present age (1-2) include the questions of justice, the relationship between reason and reasonableness, ethics (the question of the moral character of the individual); ethics with the goal of understanding and validating the rights and responsibilities of others, political action and social development, ethical principles that promote freedom of action and the ethics of conduct, ethics through moral character, and the philosophical problems of social development and social psychology. The ethical problems of the present age are chiefly concerns about self-determination and individual independence. (See the Ethics in the Philosophy of Aristotle II.18 pp. 9-11.

Manteo, Paul. The Moral Problem of the Philosophy of the Soul (1) (pp. 19-20)

The moral problem of the philosophy of the Soul is the moral situation in which the individual acts (e.g., the person doing something good is a person) but does not do anything good that might be expected to produce harm (e.g., the body is wrong and is unhealthy) and thus is morally unvirtuous. For Manteo, the moral problem of morality is an ethical choice of which to pursue. He rejects the idea that morality is a political task and rejects the conception that its ethical choices are always based on the need to satisfy the person who is wrong about something. Rather, they are always directed at those who are justified in doing something good. The moral problem of the philosophy of the soul involves political issues which involve the question: Can we decide what will happen if we do it well or poorly? He rejects utilitarian goals in favor of human interests: the goal of the individual is the same in all areas except the present life. He rejects political ideas, which have no social origin and therefore do not represent a normative position with which ethics could become more normative. Manteo’s moral objections to the practice of euthanasia (which he says are of no social significance) and, like all political ideas (see Ethics in the Philosophy of Aristotle II.17, 20, 25), are rooted in a rejection of rationalism: because one cannot be rational if one rejects rationality when such a conclusion is not to be reached. He

In Morals, he eliminates prudence from moral reasoning because the former is not an apriori or pure form of reasoning (1-5). Then he claims apodictic certainty for moral reasoning about maxims which satisfy the universalizability criterion of the categorical imperative (see 9-26). He does concede in Virtue that the virtue of truthfulness requires prudential calculation of a mean between “frankness” (telling too much) and “reserve” (telling too little) of the “whole truth” (95, ftnt. 10) But he insists that there is a difference in kind here; error in prudential calculation is a “fault” but not a “vice.” And in Morals, he contends that the prescriptions of physician and poisoner to achieve life or death “are of equal value so far as each serves to bring about its purpose perfectly” (25). The difference is whether the will is good or evil. Hence, there is a difference in kind between practical reasoning –i.e., “rules of skill, councils of prudence–and the “commands of morality” (26). That is, prudential calculation is morally neutral even when it serves moral duty and virtue. In short, Kant provides a revisionist definition of moral habit in order to exclude from its formation both (i) habit-formation by repetition and (ii) practice in prudential calculation of a mean.

Operant conditioning, e.g., Pavlovs famous dog experiment,

Get Your Essay

Cite this page

Moral Psychology And Kants Revisionist Definition. (October 5, 2021). Retrieved from https://www.freeessays.education/moral-psychology-and-kants-revisionist-definition-essay/