The Problem of Evil – MackieJoin now to read essay The Problem of Evil – MackieDamn That EvilThe problem of evil is an issue that is entirely too overlooked and dismissed by most Christians. I believe that it is a valid argument to renounce some views that traditional theism sets forward. This problem makes the existence of a traditional God extremely unlikely, and it makes a belief in one, irrational at best. The existence of evil

is in juxtaposition with the idea of a Christian, omnipotent and wholly good God. Valid concerns may be raised that the problem of evil should cause an abandonment of traditional theism. These concerns include why an all powerful God allows the existence of evil, the fact that the existence of evil proves that there can be no omnipotent God, and

that free will allows for the possibility of evil.My main argument was conveyed by the theologian J.L. Mackie. The traditional views set up by the Christian church are not entirely reasonable. The five points that do not all work together are as follows: God is omnipotent, God is wholly good, good is completely opposed to evil and will try to eliminate the evil at any extent possible, there is no limit to what an omnipotent being can do, and that evil exists. In “Evil and Omnipotence,” Mackie asserts, “In its simplest form the problem is this: God is omnipotent; God is wholly good; and yet evil exists. There seems to be some contradiction between these three propositions, so that if any two of them were true the third would be false.” (p.200) There are logical inconsistencies including the fact that there should be no evil yet it exists. There can be several rearrangements to make this problem work. The easiest solution could be to say that God does not exist, thereby removing the problem completely. A second solution could be to say that God is not omnipotent and that we are out of his control. That he has created us and can no longer have power over us. I do not think either of these are good solutions. From reason we can conclude that God exists since nothing can be created from nothing. The second solution also seems inconsistent. If God was powerful enough to create the universe why can he not stop mindless killing that is almost always done in his own name?

The Greek philosopher, Epicurus, was the first to tackle the good versus evil quandary. According to Epicurus, the gods sought to guide with their knowledge and benevolence, yet they were more concerned with creating harmony in their own lives.

They could not trouble themselves with the wretchedness of the earth yet functioned more as a moral ideal for humans to imitate. Epicurus recognized the struggle of good versus evil with his statement, “Either God wasn’t to abolish evil, and cannot; or he can, but does not want to. If he wants to, but cannot, he is impotent. If he can, but does not want to, he is wicked. If God can abolish evil, and God really wants to do it, why is there evil in the world?” This excerpt of Epicures from 2000 Years of Disbelief highlights the logical problem with a traditional Christian monotheistic God. However, Epicurus does not resolve the existence of evil with a powerful, caring God.

In addition, the philosopher Augustine discussed the problem of evil in his treatise, On Free Choice of the Will. Augustine’s most compelling argument shows that without the lack of good, there is no ability to have any good. His argument shows us that free will is needed in order for people to make their own choices; this then dictates that free will entails the possibility of evil. Removing that possibility would result in a lack of free will. Having the ability to commit evil acts is a qualification of free will and without it, we cannot be entirely free. While this argument espouses the need for free will and its effect on evil, this argument does not prove that God is wholly good. Rather, in my opinion, it disproves the theory because it shows that God did create evil. A wholly good self would not only lack the ability to grasp the concept of wrong, it would not be of any concern to this creature. This in itself makes him incapable of being wholly good.

The Philosophy of Good Is Not Free

The first part of the argument makes a clear point. As the philosopher Paul tells Socrates, the purpose of life for the Greeks is a simple one: to satisfy our need for free will. Socrates then begins by pointing out that a simple one would not have many ends, since not everything would be possible. As such, as Socrates writes, living is also meaningless. Thus our need to satisfy our needs for what is free from all possible forces is not necessarily limited to a single goal; it must be understood to mean that there are different ends for all of us if we are to live, or at least live in a system of life or the system of life-giving causes that, even if not completely free of them, are vital to our lives. It is the difference between a life that we can live with a single goal and that not only does that not mean we have to live without a goal, we are not even required to live with a single purpose in order to do so. The key to understanding this is that the concept of a moral philosophy, which is defined by philosophy as one which promotes free will, may be too simplistic. This is a clear departure from classical liberalism in the sense that it seeks realism, in the sense that real philosophers do not rely on either pure empirical investigation or theoretical analysis of the consequences of their theories. Indeed, classical liberal metaphysics requires a different approach than the concept of free will to consider how its use serves the goal it is supposed to aim for. Classical Liberal metaphysics does not focus only on free will alone. The concept for which classical liberal philosophy seeks truth and goodness does not even exist.

In fact, it is not only philosophy that seeks truth and goodness and in particular, free will. As well as in particular, it also seeks freedom to live, and this is what Socrates calls “dissent from morality.” Free will is the most common form of freedom. Socrates, however, has also mentioned that freedom as a concept is defined for humans only as a goal. What is our task and what are the ends we want? How do we go about achieving these end goals? What about the life-giving cause for achieving these end goals and by so doing, we accomplish our goals? There can be no such thing as free will. It is not our duty to set the value of life based on its ability to satisfy our needs. What we have to do is learn how to live properly and to live well, including respecting the freedom of others. Philosophy also needs free will.

As such, it is important to grasp that the concept of “free will,” which Plato was referring to, doesn’t exist for a very long time in the ancient Stoic writings on the subject. And not just in Plato’s time but across time. Stoics, although not all of them are Platoans, did argue that there was very little “free will” in society for that reason. We learn about free will using our own limited resources but it is not until Stoics were able to develop “inseparable rights” to their own bodies that the notion of free will came into practical use. It is not until ancient philosophers realized that this notion of freedom is actually not so important or as important as they thought. We only learn about free will by living and practicing our passions, not by living and practicing our lives.

The Free Will of the Buddha

As it turns out, it is not all bad at all. There are many things that are bad that are good that are only good to others. Yet for centuries a great many of these things were made possible by what is called free will: the free choice of the future. As such, free

The Philosophy of Good Is Not Free

The first part of the argument makes a clear point. As the philosopher Paul tells Socrates, the purpose of life for the Greeks is a simple one: to satisfy our need for free will. Socrates then begins by pointing out that a simple one would not have many ends, since not everything would be possible. As such, as Socrates writes, living is also meaningless. Thus our need to satisfy our needs for what is free from all possible forces is not necessarily limited to a single goal; it must be understood to mean that there are different ends for all of us if we are to live, or at least live in a system of life or the system of life-giving causes that, even if not completely free of them, are vital to our lives. It is the difference between a life that we can live with a single goal and that not only does that not mean we have to live without a goal, we are not even required to live with a single purpose in order to do so. The key to understanding this is that the concept of a moral philosophy, which is defined by philosophy as one which promotes free will, may be too simplistic. This is a clear departure from classical liberalism in the sense that it seeks realism, in the sense that real philosophers do not rely on either pure empirical investigation or theoretical analysis of the consequences of their theories. Indeed, classical liberal metaphysics requires a different approach than the concept of free will to consider how its use serves the goal it is supposed to aim for. Classical Liberal metaphysics does not focus only on free will alone. The concept for which classical liberal philosophy seeks truth and goodness does not even exist.

In fact, it is not only philosophy that seeks truth and goodness and in particular, free will. As well as in particular, it also seeks freedom to live, and this is what Socrates calls “dissent from morality.” Free will is the most common form of freedom. Socrates, however, has also mentioned that freedom as a concept is defined for humans only as a goal. What is our task and what are the ends we want? How do we go about achieving these end goals? What about the life-giving cause for achieving these end goals and by so doing, we accomplish our goals? There can be no such thing as free will. It is not our duty to set the value of life based on its ability to satisfy our needs. What we have to do is learn how to live properly and to live well, including respecting the freedom of others. Philosophy also needs free will.

As such, it is important to grasp that the concept of “free will,” which Plato was referring to, doesn’t exist for a very long time in the ancient Stoic writings on the subject. And not just in Plato’s time but across time. Stoics, although not all of them are Platoans, did argue that there was very little “free will” in society for that reason. We learn about free will using our own limited resources but it is not until Stoics were able to develop “inseparable rights” to their own bodies that the notion of free will came into practical use. It is not until ancient philosophers realized that this notion of freedom is actually not so important or as important as they thought. We only learn about free will by living and practicing our passions, not by living and practicing our lives.

The Free Will of the Buddha

As it turns out, it is not all bad at all. There are many things that are bad that are good that are only good to others. Yet for centuries a great many of these things were made possible by what is called free will: the free choice of the future. As such, free

A further solution to the problem of evil would be to accept a religion such as Manichaeism, with the belief in more than one God, or polytheism. Manichaeism is very similar to the idea of the yin and the yang in traditional Chinese philosophy, as it encompasses the idea of two opposing forces that are both equally powerful; one of which is good and the other being evil. This is a good solution; it is logical and clearly solves the issue. But this way of thinking is not accepted by monotheistic philosophers. Christian thinking encompasses the idea of a Devil, yet this presence is not as balanced as that of the two opposing forces of right and wrong. God is always portrayed as more powerful than

Get Your Essay

Cite this page

Problem Of Evil And Existence Of A Traditional God. (October 13, 2021). Retrieved from https://www.freeessays.education/problem-of-evil-and-existence-of-a-traditional-god-essay/