Risk and Risk Aversion
Lecture 1: Risk and Risk AversionThis should mostly be review given your Microeconomics coursesReadings:Ingersoll – Chapter 1Leroy and Werner Chapters 8 & 9Ross – “Stronger Measures of Risk Aversion”The most interesting aspect of Asset Pricing, the focus of this course, considers how securities markets price risk (the time dimension alone is largely mechanical although there are interesting interactions between the two). For this question to be interesting, it must be that there is a positive price for risk – i.e. investors require some compensation for exposing their portfolios to risk (this certainly appears to be true from the data). Theoretically, this in turn requires that investors dislike risk or that they are risk averse. For intuition’s sake, we will review some of the relevant concepts.Definition: Let [pic 1]be a preference relation with an expected utility representation. [pic 2] is said to exhibit or display risk aversion if for any simple gamble [pic 3] with expected value g, denoted [pic 4], the relation weakly prefers the fixed value g to the simple gamble → g [pic 5] [pic 6] [pic 7]g, [pic 8]. The weak preference allows for indifference so “weak risk aversion” includes risk neutrality. (Strict risk aversion, risk neutrality, and risk seeking (weak or strict) are defined analogously.)
Example: A simple gamble: Consider a random payoff [pic 9] which pays [pic 10] > 0 with probability 1 ≥ p ≥ 0 or [pic 11] ≠ [pic 12] with probability 1 – p. The expected value of [pic 13] is p[pic 14]+ (1-p)[pic 15] = E([pic 16]) = g. This gamble is said to be ‘fair’ if E[[pic 17]] = g = 0. We can alternatively define a risk averse agent as one who is unwilling or indifferent to taking any fair gamble, and strictly risk averse if unwilling to accept any fair gamble. In the above definition, a risk averse individual (weakly) prefers to receive the amount E([pic 18]) = g rather than face the bet [pic 19].